Judging and Understanding
From historycooperative.org/journals/lhr/19.1/bilsky2.html
LEORA BILSKY
What is the relationship between judging and understanding? Does
the process of understanding undermine our ability to judge? Or
maybe the contrary is true, that judgment is possible only when
its subject is understandable? If judgment requires distance and
understanding requires empathy (overcoming distance), is there an
inherent impossibility in trying to judge the Holocaust by trying
to understand it? Language itself betrays a sense in which
understanding and judgment conflict. The popular saying tout
comprendre c'est tout pardonner rings true in our everyday
experiences. What are we to do when the subject of our inquiry is
of such moral magnitude that understanding becomes a duty we owe
to ourselves, and yet any progress in understanding seems to be
meaningless if it does not enhance our capacity of judgment. The
two thoughtful responses by David Luban and Lawrence Douglas to
my essay "Judging Evil in the Trial of Kastner" are
directed at disentangling this complex relationship between
judgment and understanding. Luban asks for more judgment. Douglas
insists on more understanding.
1
Writing his report to the Jewish
Agency about the efforts to save the Jews of Hungary, Kastner
anticipates these questions and cautions:
2
It was a slippery slope that almost always led to destruction.
Everywhere the Jew was faced with the same problem: should I be
the traitor so that here and there I'll be able to help or even
be the savior, the rescuer, or should I abandon the community to
its fate and let others decide its fate? Is not the flight from
responsibility merely another kind of betrayal? And if I do take
this upon myself, what is the line that I should never cross?
Should I release myself from responsibility at the cost of
destroying myself through suicide or being executed? Common sense
is almost incapable of drawing the line between self-sacrifice
and betrayal. It is not surprising then, that in every place that
still had a Jewish community this question was raised again and
again. To judge the Judenrate after the fact, on the basis of
testimonies, documents and sources--this is a task that is beyond
the capacity of any human tribunal.1
The epistemic and moral crisis that was left in the wake of the
Holocaust confronts the judge with the limits of law, literature,
and historiography.2 As Kastner reminds us, the Jewish Councils
had to make their judgments of where to draw the line without the
perspective of time and under immense pressures from their Jewish
communities and from the Nazis commanders. This puts them in the
"gray zone," as Luban rightly observes.
The Israeli court had to address
this phenomenon when judging Kastner's efforts to save the Jews
of Hungary as vice president of the Rescue Committee, especially
in regard to what is known as the Kastner train.3 I discussed two
decisions, the one by Judge Halevi of the Jerusalem District
Court and the other by Justice Agranat of the Supreme Court. I
argued that these judgments are revealing not only because of
their opposing conclusions about Kastner's guilt, but more
importantly because of the ways in which the judges attempted to
overcome the epistemic and moral crisis they were facing. This
approach allowed me to shift the emphasis from the familiar
question of which field is better suited to the task of judgment
(literature, history, law) to the less explored question of how
we go about judging a radically new phenomenon. Surprisingly, it
turned out that in confronting the novel and often
incomprehensible facts of the Holocaust, the judges relied
heavily on our common cultural heritage of law, history, and
literature. Moreover, success or failure here depended less on
which metaphor was used but rather on the creative and sensitive
use the judge made of his chosen metaphor in order to reach
beyond his own world. Thus, the Faust metaphor as it had been
developed by Goethe and Mann could have helped explore the
"gray zone" of action where good intentions result in
evil deeds, but it was used instead by Judge Halevi to turn the
gray shadings of Kastner's actions into a black-and-white
morality play. Likewise, contract law could have been used to
demonstrate the conditions of illegality, inequality, force, and
deception under which Kastner and Brand had negotiated with
Eichmann, but it was used instead to create an omnipotent actor
out of Kastner. For this reason I do not believe that there is
one correct answer to the question of which legal or literary
metaphors best capture the ambiguities of the "gray
zone." The crucial factor is how these metaphors are used to
shed light on the historical context under consideration. My
response, therefore, is intended to clarify not my choice of
metaphor but my evaluation of the use made by the court of the
different metaphors.
3
In Judge Halevi's decision I
focused on the contract metaphor and the Faustian story. Douglas
argues that although the Faustian metaphor is very powerful, its
"Fleeting invocation . . . by Halevi can hardly serve as an
example of the kind of robust engagement with the world of
literature that Martha Nussbaum and Richard Weisberg believe
would humanize legal discourse."4 However, I sought to show
how this metaphor was not a momentary allusion happened upon by
the judge but rather revealed the underlying perceptions that
shaped the entire narrative of the court and consequently the
moral condemnation of Kastner. Halevi relied heavily on literary
images of evil doing (Faust and the Trojan Horse) and skillfully
developed them in order to demonstrate the unique nature of
Jewish collaboration with the Nazis (a combination of fraudulent
gifts and contractual obligations). And yet, these same literary
sensitivities blinded him to the complexity and ambiguity of the
historical circumstances under which Kastner had acted. In this
way Kastner (K. in Halevi's opinion) could be made into a symbol
of the Judenrate member, devoid of human face and stranger to the
fragility of the human condition. This is why Halevi's judgment
serves as an interesting counterexample to Nussbaum's model of
judgment.
4
Luban, on the other hand, while
conceding the centrality of the contract metaphor to Halevi's
judgment, wonders whether the cumulative force of the other
episodes (such as the paratroopers' affair and Kastner's
affidavit in support of Kurt Becher) do not tilt the balance
against Kastner nevertheless.5 I believe they do not. In another
article devoted to the politicization of the trial by defense
attorney Shmuel Tamir, I discuss at length the paratroopers'
affair and how it was misrepresented in the court.6 Here I will
just note that historians have concluded that the Gestapo's
information about the paratroopers came not from Kastner but
probably from their Hungarian contacts.7 Learning that the
paratroopers were under surveillance, Kastner explained to them
that by contacting him they endangered the entire rescue efforts
regarding the train. Still, Kastner and other members of the
Rescue Committee left it to the paratroopers themselves to decide
how to act (whether to hide, run away, or surrender to the
Gestapo). The paratroopers' affair reveals to what extent the
Yishuv's conception of heroic action was ill fit to the reality
of conquered Europe, a tragic realization that was later shared
by Palgi and his heroic friends. Moreover, from a legal point of
view, since Gruenvald's pamphlet did not deal with the
paratroopers' affair, it was irrelevant to the libel case.8 The
Becher affair deserves more consideration of whether Kastner's
fault stemmed mainly from lying about his affidavit in the court,
or whether it was morally unacceptable to give an affidavit in
support of a Nazi officer whose greed (and need of alibi) had
facilitated the committee's efforts of rescue at the time.
5
Agranat's judgment raises a more
difficult question, since it is here that I Find a more
constructive attempt at judging the "gray zone." Luban
has two reservations about the value of applying administrative
law to Kastner's actions. On the one hand, he claims that since
Kastner was not a public official he "had no political
mandate for engaging in utilitarian calculation involving the
life of the community"; and, on the other hand, he argues
that "the whole question of what is reasonable under such
insane circumstances . . . seems profoundly unanswerable."9
I disagree on both points. Kastner was certainly not acting as a
private agent but as a representative of the Zionist movement, as
vice-president of the Rescue Committee.10 Although at the time
the Zionists constituted a minority among the Jews of Hungary,
nonetheless, unlike other segments of the Jewish community, they
were not paralyzed by the Nazi occupation and sought ways to
influence the Jews' fate.11 Kastner, unlike the representative of
the Orthodox Jews (Fulop von Freudiger), for example, did not
flee.12 It is true that Kastner was not a Judenrate member
appointed by the Nazis, but in this case it is the authority that
he acquired in the eyes of the Jewish community when negotiating
on their behalf that is the crucial factor. These were among the
reasons that convinced Justice Agranat to attribute to Kastner
the duties of a public official.13 The second question that Luban
raises about the criteria of judging Kastner's actions is more
difficult. One interpretation of Luban's objection might be that
the "reasonableness" or rationality of Kastner's
actions simply cannot be judged, but this seems to go against the
central point that Luban takes from Primo Levi, that is, that
"remaining agnostic in the face of evil is a defeat."14
It is more likely, therefore, that Luban deems Kastner's actions
as profoundly unreasonable because, as he writes, the
probabilities were tiny and the consequences enormous.15 But
could it not be the case that in such extreme circumstances when
all norms of behavior had collapsed, when the inconceivable had
become reality, when the "unreasonable" ruled, the
"unreasonable" way was the only option and hence should
be judged by us today as reasonable?
6
An Israeli historian has suggested
that in order to better understand the epistemic crisis of
judging the Holocaust, historians should attempt to adopt the
viewpoint of the Judenrate.16 From this perspective we begin to
grasp how the Jewish leaders' attempts to use utilitarian
calculation in judging the Nazis' intentions were genuine and
inevitable, but at the same time, trapped them and led to
failure. The rational calculation of trying to avert the worst
evil by means of the least evil constantly changed and in the end
backfired. Studying the Judenrate attempts at evaluating the
Nazis' intentions reveals in a striking way how rationality was
transformed by the Nazis into counterrationality. Agranat's
method of judgment--his attempt to put himself in Kastner's
shoes--enables us to retain this sense of dissonance between our
rationality and the counterrationality of those times. It can
serve as a key to understanding the abyss that the Holocaust
presents to us.
7
I believe that we should retain an
awareness of the abyss when we form our judgments of the people
who occupied the "gray zone" of the Holocaust. What
made Kastner able to act in the face of minuscule probabilities
and enormous dangers was precisely his tendency to exaggerate,
his egotism, his willingness to embark on illegal activities, and
yes, even his Zionism, which led him to "think big" and
creatively. And yet, ironically, these same qualities doomed him
in the Israeli court of law. The "gray zone" of black
times can easily be mistaken for black deeds in brighter times.
8
Notes
1 Israel Kastner, Report of the Rescue Committee in Budapest,
19421945 (submitted to the Zionist Congress), 108 [Hebrew].
Cited by Judge Halevi, Cr.C. (Jm.) 124/53 Attorney General v.
Gruenvald, 44 P.M. (1965) 3, at 115 [my translation, L.B.].
2 Saul Friedlander, ed., Probing the Limits of Representation
(Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1992).
3 The exact number of passengers remains unclear according to the
different sources. Bauer mentions 1684, Segev--1685, and
Weitz--1685. See Yehuda Bauer, Jews for Sale? Jewish
Negotiations, 19331945 (New Haven: Yale University Press,
1994), 198, 199; Tom Segev, The Seventh Million: The Israelis and
the Holocaust, trans. Haim Watzman (New York: Hill and Wang,
1993), 265; Yehiam Weitz, Ha-Ish she-Nirtsah Paamayim [The Man
Who Was Murdered Twice] (Jerusalem: Keter, 1995), 33. In the
appeal, the figure was given as 1684 (Cr.A. [Jm.] 232/55 Attorney
General v. Gruenvald, 1958 [12] P.D. 2017, at 2046, 2048). Maybe
the source of the confusion is Kastner's own report (Report of
the Rescue Committee) that states at one point that the number
was 1685 (47) and in other places that it was 1684 (105, 115).
4 Lawrence Douglas, "Language, Judgment, and the
Holocaust," Law and History Review 19 (2001): 178.
5 David Luban, "A Man Lost in the Gray Zone," Law and
History Review 19 (2001): 168.
6 Leora Bilsky, "Performing the Past: The Politicization of
the Holocaust in the Kastner Trial," in Lethe's Law, ed.
Emilios Christodoulidis (forthcoming).
7 Weitz, Ha-Ish she-Nirtsah Paamayim, 3940.
8 Appeal, Attorney General v. Gruenvald, 2179.
9 Luban, "A Man Lost in the Gray Zone," 173.
10 Indeed, this is the reason that he was under an obligation to
submit a report on their rescue efforts to the Zionist Congress
in 1946.
11 Bauer, Jews for Sale? 15455
12 The fact that many of his relatives and friends from his
hometown Kluj were included in the train can be attributed to the
Nazis' well-known manipulative technique. In many cases they
showed more willingness to save the families of the Jewish
functionaries in order to increase their dependence on them.
Maybe, as a public official, Kastner should have refused to go
along with this. But, from a moral point of view, the answer to
this question is unclear. Indeed, Neil Gordon's novel The
Sacrifice of Isaac (New York: Random House, 1995) presents the
opposite scenario (a Zionist, given certificates by the Nazis to
rescue his older relatives, replaces them with young men) and
raises difficult moral questions that stem from this decision.
13 Agranat's opinion, Appeal, Attorney General v. Gruenvald,
2080: "As a result of the committee's connections with the
Jewish Agency and the Joint on the one hand, and its contacts
with the 'Juden Commando' on the other, it acquired in the eyes
of the Jews of Hungary the status of the authoritative Jewish
body in all matters relating to protecting their lives and
rescuing them. For this reason, it is evident that the moral duty
that Kastner owed to the Jews of Hungary derived from the
public--if you will the political--functions he was charged with
fulfilling" [my translation, emphasis in the original,
L.B.].
14 Luban, "A Man Lost in the Gray Zone," 163.
15 Ibid., 174.
16 Dan Diner, "History and Counter-Rationality--The
'Judenrate' as a Point of View," Zmanim 53 (1995): 4553.